OK, gotta get to the point.
Jonathan and my contribution to the vast (ie non-existent) scholarly field of quincunx studies was this: we wondered what would happen if some of the pins in the quincunx didn’t have a 50-50 chance of bouncing the balls right or left. Because that is what GWAS is about, isn’t it? Everyone is born with a whole lot of pins (SNPs) and each of them has some tendency to bounce us more in the direction of divorce or more in the direction of marital bliss. Then a single ball falls down our personal quincunx (we only get one life) and winds up in a bin (the phenotype). The goal of GWAS is to find correlations between which pins you have and your phenotype, and (the important part) to use those correlations to infer the causal properties of the pins, that is their tendency to bounce people toward or away from divorce.
There is plenty of reason to expect this to be a dicey process. Suppose I have an A (as in ACTG) pin in the third row of my personal quincunx, and it has a 52% chance of bouncing me left. It’s a left-bias pin, amirite? But now suppose that in the next row, just on the left, I happen have a G pin that is strongly, (say 80%) biased to bounce to the right. Is the first pin still left biased? Yes it bounces balls left, but the net effect is to move things to the right, because (in my personal quincunx genome) it interacts with the right-biased pin below it. There is no way to describe all this without sounding a bit silly, but I insist that all this talk about pins in quincunx is, if anything, a vast simplification of what must happen in terms of genetic influences on human behavioral development.
So in the second paper, linked here, we actually build simulated quincunx with biased pins, drop a single ball down each of them, and conduct a GWAS. The details are in the paper, but the conclusion is: quincunx-GWAS doesn’t work. Specifically, it detects SNP hits, ie correlations between which SNPs you have and where your ball ends up, but the magnitude, and even the sign, of those correlations has essentially 0 relationship with the actual bounce-biases of the pins. In regular GWAS language, one would say that the magnitude and sign of the SNP hits don’t correspond to the real causal consequences of the SNPs (which in real GWAS are unknown; inferring them is the point, or at least one point, of the exercise.)
OK, getting close. Even under these discouraging circumstances in terms of causation, heritability still happens. Two balls dropped down identical quincunx (MZ twins) are much more likely to wind up in the same bin than balls dropped down quincunx that only share half their pins (DZ twins or siblings). Less similar for “half-siblings,” “cousins” and so forth in quincunx extended families. This is how heritability is typically estimated in humans, as the slope of the line relating genotypic similarity on the X-axis and phenotypic similarity on the Y. I show in my book how this is the easiest way to derive the Falconer formula for twin heritability.
Here is the key insight for now, especially for strong heritability doubters like Jay Joseph and
. Even though there is no straightforward causal relationship between individual SNPs and behavioral outcomes, it is nonetheless true that organisms with more similar SNPs in general wind up with more similar phenotypes in general. These two ideas are hard to hold in the head at the same time, but they are both true. There are no genes that predispose to divorce, but people with similar genomes are more likely to have similar marital status.And finally, tomorrow, the kicker: the relationship between genotypic and phenotypic similarity isn’t linear. This is the explanation of missing heritability.
Eric,
First--I devoured your book and loved it. In my (recent) training as a sociologist, the heritability/twins/GWAS work that I encountered (only peripherally) never quite made sense to me. "Stuck in my craw". I think I just didn't have a good mental model to understand them. Reading your book, I finally feel some lights coming on. So thank you.
Second, on this post and this paper: fantastic, it gives me a more concrete grasp on many points in the book, and what might be happening between GWAS and twin studies.
One point that you don't explicitly make, but I wonder about. The possibly massive interactivity of the whole system--among genes and between genes and life events--presents a dimensionality problem, a la the "curse of dimensionality". It may be that even if you could get every living human into a GWAS (or even, every human who has ever lived!), you would not have enough data to develop a good predictive model of many complex behavioral outcomes. And the problem is even worse than that, because as you add more people, I imagine the way outcomes themselves are defined will start to drift and blur. Ah, but maybe I'm just restating your "gloomy prospect"?
Anyway, thanks again for your excellent work.
Noah
Appreciate the shout out, Eric. It seems that there are a multitude of ways I could respond to this, but I’m not completely clear on your claim. It appears the Quincunx didn’t work (for the reasons I predicted when you brought it up on Twitter, as I recall). So as I understand it, you are saying it can’t predict phenotype from a heritability standpoint except if we have identical twins (or identical Quincunxes). I don’t know where your next installment is going with this, but I will try to preempt it by noting that the whole point of behavioral genetics was to examine high heritability of psychiatric diagnoses, personality traits and IQ. Yet, you are not successful in even developing a coherent mathematical model to explain this, even with some stochastic elements thrown in. In other words, you are negating the primary purpose of your field or at least not confirming it. So if the Quincunx model only works for identical twins, it seems like a failed model. If I say that non pathological genetic variants are not causal for psychiatric disorders, your Quincunx experiment doesn’t contradict that unless the Quincunx is identical. So again, we are back to identical twins being all that you got. Moreover, that’s only theoretical. The fact that identical twins are more alike and the results of identical quincunxes are more consistent, doesn’t prove that the Quincunx model is accurate and, in fact, is contradicted by the non identical Quincunx failure. Thus, my assertion that behavioral genetics is largely a null field remains on the table, 30 years running.